Hot Air

Steve Levitt and Steve Dubner, the SuperFreakonomics guys (formerly the Freakonomics guys) have raised a lot of temperatures with their chapter on global warming. The backlash began with Paul Krugman, who in turn was neatly skewered by several authors, but most effectively by the journalist Ari Armstrong.

The critics have raised two objections that come perilously close to contradicting each other: First, Levitt and Dubner are accused of minimizing the problem. Second, they are accused of overeagerness to solve the problem, as opposed to, say, demonizing the responsible parties. Of these, only the first deserves to be taken seriously.

Among the more serious critics is the world’s funniest economist, Yoram Bauman. In an email exchange with Levitt, Bauman scores the first point. Levitt has left himself wide open with the Superfreaky observation that carbon dioxide generated by human activity is only a small percentage of what’s already circulating through the atmosphere. As Bauman rightly observes, this is a bogus comparison, because unlike human-generated emissions, circulating CO2 adds nothing to the total accumulation. It’s a little like observing that the water flowing into my bathtub each minute is only a small percentage of what’s already sloshing around in there. That observation has no bearing on whether I’m headed for a flood.

But this criticism applies to four ill-chosen lines in a 45 page chapter. I find most of Bauman’s other criticisms less compelling. Yes, the chapter opens by recalling the media-driven global cooling scare of the 1970s. Yes, a careless reader might conclude that Levitt and Dubner equate today’s legitimate concern about global warming with that brief episode of media hype. But such a reader would have to gloss over passages such as this one: “There is essentially a consensus among climate scientists that the earth’s temperature has been rising and, increasingly, agreement that human activity has played an important role.” The same reader would have to miss the citation to Marty Weitzman’s estimate that we face a (rather staggering) 5% chance of global catastrophe. And most of all, that reader would have to somehow not notice that the bulk of the chapter is a paean to people who are trying to solve this problem.

So despite Bauman’s undeniable zinger, I am inclined to (largely) absolve Levitt and Dubner of excessive skepticism or of understating the potential problem. Instead, I object to the economic errors that nobody else seems to have mentioned. Starting here:

In principle, this shouldn’t be such a hard problem. If we knew how much it cost humankind every time someone used a tank of gas, we could simply levy a tax of that magnitude on the driver. The tax wouldn’t necessarily convince him to cancel his trip, nor should it. The point of the tax is to make sure the driver faces the full cost of his actions (or, in economist-speak, to internalize the externality.)

This would be correct if all the costs were felt immediately. But as it is, calculating the right tax requires a judgment call about how heavily to weight the interests of future generations. That’s fundamentally a philosophical issue, not an economic one—but it can’t be ignored. And it is a hard problem.

The great philospher/economist/mathematician Frank Ramsey, who plays a large role in The Big Questions, believed it was an ethical imperative to treat future generations’ interests as equivalent to our own. It was this position that led the authors of the Stern report to approve the prospect of massive anti-warming expenditures. But the same position dictates a massive increase in saving and a drastic reform of the tax system to incentivize that massive increase. In other words, we’ve never adopted the Ramsey position to guide any other policy; why, then, should we suddenly adopt it now?

Indeed, in The Big Questions (pages 186-189) I’ve argued for the exact opposite of Ramsey’s position—putting zero weight on the interests of future generations. I’m not sure this argument is right, but I’m not sure it’s wrong either.

I can’t criticize Levitt and Dubner’s stand on this issue, because they take no stand—which is fine; for what they’re doing, they don’t need to. But without taking a stand they can’t correctly claim that it’s in principle an easy matter to calculate the right gas tax.

That’s not, however, the biggest economic error in this chapter. That occurs in an absolutely bizarre (but fortunately tangential) paragraph where black lung disease is offered as an example of an environmental externality. In italics even:

In the United States alone, more than 100,000 coal miners died on the job over the past century, with another estimated 200,000 dying later from black lung disease. Now those are externalities.

Umm. No, they’re not, actually, as I hope anyone who’s passed my freshman economics course could tell you. Black lung disease is a huge and horrible cost of coal mining but it’s not an external cost for the simple reason that it falls on coal miners. The one and only defining characteristic of an externality is that it falls on someone who was never a party to the transaction that created it.

Well, never mind, that paragraph has no bearing on the thrust of the chapter. But I have to wonder how it could have survived the editing process.

The final two thirds or so of the chapter is devoted to a lively and engaging survey of some extremely inventive and potentially cheap solutions, some of which involve helium filled balloons, which makes me happy. Levitt and Dubner don’t claim to know what will work and what won’t (if they did, they’d deserve a lot more ridicule than they’re getting), but they do claim this stuff is worth thinking about, which seems to be obviously true. I’m sure that some of the negative response comes from knowledgeable skeptics, but I suspect that more of it comes from people who don’t want there to be cheap solutions.

There’s one cheap solution, though, that gets too little play here: Let the earth warm up and live with the consequences, which seems likely to be cheaper than a Stern-sized prevention plan. Suppose, for example, that we had to move New York City inland within a century. That’s an expensive prospect, but less so than you might think. Over the next century we’re going to be rebuilding most of New York City anyway, since few buildings last 100 years. The cost of global warming is not the cost of rebuilding the entire city; it’s the additional cost of building it in one place rather than another. (I am grateful to David Friedman for inspiring this observation. And yes, I realize that there are serious coordination problems that I’ve left unmentioned, but the point remains. I also realize that in a worst-case scenario we might regret this plan.)

Is that the right way to go? I have no idea. I also have no idea whether any of Levitt and Dubner’s solutions will work. I do think everything should be on the table.

To avoid leaving a false impression: Despite all the criticism, some of it justified and some of it mine, the bulk of this chapter is not just unobjectionable; it’s enlightening, it’s fun to read, and it lays appropriate stress on the key point that pollution is a cost, not a sin—a problem to tackled, not an occasion to excoriate people with different priorities. I haven’t yet read the other chapters, but I suspect they’re real good too.

Print Friendly, PDF & Email
Share

8 Responses to “Hot Air”


  1. 1 1 Matt C

    Excellent review Steve. My reaction from reading their chapter as well. It’s a fun and engaging read that introduces many issues I was not aware of. It’s not meant to be an academic piece. The critics need to lighten up.

  2. 2 2 David Friedman

    One further point is worth mentioning, given the reference to a low but significant chance of catastrophe. Given the present state of knowledge, a low but significant chance of catastrophe also exists in the other direction.

    We are currently in an interglacial. Interglacials typically last about ten thousand years, with a good deal of variation. As a very crude back of the envelope estimate, that gives us one chance in ten thousand each year that the interglacial will end–or about a one percent chance in a century.

    A mile of ice over the present locations of Chicago and London, and a sea level drop of hundreds of feet, I think classifies as catastrophe. It’s at least possible that global warming due to human action is what is currently preventing it.

  3. 3 3 Cody

    What? How are the positions “Levitt and Dubner equate today’s legitimate concern about global warming with that brief episode of media hype” and “There is essentially a consensus among climate scientists that the earth’s temperature has been rising and, increasingly, agreement that human activity has played an important role” at all contradictory? Isn’t the second statement in fact a prerequisite for believing the first?

  4. 4 4 Phil

    Cody -the global cooling hype was not a broad consensus, and apparently was just a few people. Today’s gw science is better accepted and represents a lot of scientists. I am not such a scientist, but that is what I read.

  5. 5 5 greenfyre

    “First, Levitt and Dubner are accused of minimizing the problem.”

    Not in the least, they are principally criticized having conducted shoddy, lazy research that resulted in a book chapter that is error filled nonsense, as is well documented at the many links collected here:
    http://leftasanexercise.simulating-reality.com/?p=90
    Building on that foundation, is it any wonder that their discussion and conclusions are drivel?

  6. 6 6 Cody

    Right, but Levitt and Dubner don’t present the global cooling episode as media hype. They seem to be implying that there was a scientific consensus in each case and the scientists were wrong the first time. This is the problem critics have with it, and is why pointing out that Levitt and Dubner say there is a broad scientific consensus now does little to respond to these critics.

  7. 7 7 Zach

    The climate change chapter really needs to be looked at in the context of the rest of the book. It’s like the last chapter in a textbook, they explore how principles discussed earlier can be applied to this new problem.

    Geoengineering, for example, is treated as a possible cheap bottom up solution to what appears as an expensive and intractable problem when addressed from the top down. Their introduction gives an historical example of just such a solution (automobiles completely eliminating the problem of horse manure in growing cities). Their discussion of how television has improved the lives of Indian women can be seen as another example.

    The power of bottom up innovation compared to top down planning was probably the strongest theme of the book but there are others that show up throughout the book that return in chapter 5.

    Another theme is how hard it can be to get people to do what they know is right, much less getting them to behave altruistically. Feied’s story of the difficulty of getting modern day doctors to wash their hands is directly related to how difficult it will be to get people to change their consumption habits in order to reduce CO2.

    Seriously, read the first four chapters then re-read chapter 5. It gives you a completely different perspective and makes their choice of climate related subjects far less controversial. Looked at holistically, their choices in chapter 5 make sense as examples of how to apply earlier tidbits of economic reasoning to the subject of global warming.

    What I was most disappointed in was a great teachable moment in their prostitution chapter. Their high priced call girl raised her rates from $300 an hour to $500 an hour with no discernible impact on demand. Immediately I thought “Cool, there could be a lot of things going on like very inelastic demand, a non competitive market or perhaps it’s a market that isn’t in equilibrium. This could be an example of a market where the supply and demand curves don’t meet for some reason.” They had an opportunity to illustrate a lot of consumption theory with that observation alone. Instead, they carry on with the story and eventually come to the conclusion that more call girls would necessarily lower prices. It felt like they dropped the ball there.

  8. 8 8 Vangel

    “First, Levitt and Dubner are accused of minimizing the problem.”

    Actually, it is the opposite. They play up to the shoddy narratives that pretend to be real science and ignore the fact that after $100 billion in spending there isn’t a single empirical study that backs up the scary predictions made by the IPCC. The pretence of consensus is not very useful because even if there were consensus on something meaningful it could simply be wrong. After all, the overwhelming consensus on eugenics, lobotomies, the causes of ulcers, the superiority of central planning, the competence and prudence of central bankers etc., all proved to be wrong.

    In the real world what matters is empirical evidence, not models or narratives. Until the IPCC and the AGW proponents can show that the feedback assumptions that create the scary warming scenarios have merit it is to be treated with the contempt that most political bureaucracies deserve. And until there is a free and open debate the AGW proponents who run from such a debate are to be dismissed as empty suits who know a lot less than they imagine.

  1. 1 Landsburg on SuperFreakonomics and Global Warming « Daniel Joseph Smith
  2. 2 Assorted Links (11/2/2009) – Jim Garven's Blog
  3. 3 In the news | Stand-Up Economist

Leave a Reply